A major challenge for intercultural philosophy:

9/11’ and its aftermath

by

Wim van Binsbergen


homepage

 

GRIPh (Groningen Research Institute of Philosophy) Lecture, Groningen, 1st June, 2005[1]

 

1. How my course on intercultural philosophy started on 9-12 (2001)

After taking over the chair of Foundations of Intercultural Philosophy at Erasmus University Rotterdam in 1998, I annually taught[2] a post-graduate course, with the same designation as the chair. Being offered in English, the course was part of the Philosophical Faculty’s so-called ‘English stream’ (now formalised in our Master’s programme), which every year attracted one to two dozen students from all over the world. In the academic year 2001-2002, my course was scheduled to start on 12th September 2001 (‘nine-twelve’). So that afternoon the lecture room filled with a heterogeneous collection of students fresh from, without a doubt, the most shocking television event of the new millennium; you may remember that the impact of the second plane into the New York World Trade Centre, twenty minutes after the first, received world-wide and practically life television coverage. The group that welcomed me that afternoon was tense, indignant, and shocked. Nearly all of them were totally new to me, and they represented a significant selection of continents: one student from sub-Saharan Africa, two from the Islamic Middle East, one from Israel, another one from the eastern Mediterranean (Greece), one from South East Asia, one from the Indian Ocean, four citizens of the United States of America, a few from the United Kingdom, one from Ireland, a few from Eastern Europe, and a handful of Dutch citizens, including some whose recent immigrant status equiped them with identitary and social links in the Middle East, South Asia, or South America. The chance composition of the group made it a sample of non-specialist world opinion. The glances and remarks exchanged across the room suggested that (with the exception of the one American girl of recent West European extraction who had married a fellow USA citizen from an Iranian Muslim background) the students were more than willing to play the parts geopolitically to be expected from them in those tense days of violent and devastating intercontinental confrontation. The original, standard purpose of that first session had been to outline the technical details of the course and to allocate specific tasks for each student, to be followed by my Revised Introductory Lecture IIIb, in which I always describe (cf. van Binsbergen 2003) my path, through the decades, from empirical social science (as a historicising anthropologist of sub-Saharan African religion and ethnicity) via a – unsettlingly subjective and exoticising – phase of anti-hegemonic and anti-objectifying criticism of North-South academic knowledge production, via comparative and theoretical research on identities and (proto-)globalisation, to intercultural philosophy. However, the miniature ad hoc world forum convened, that afternoon, in my lecture room was not only going to sit in judgment on the acts of undeclared war claiming, only the day before, the lives of several thousands of citizens on the eastern seaboard of the United States of America, against the recent historical background of the years of tension , confrontation and violence leading up to it. I felt that it was also my version of intercultural philosophy that was on trial. Would I declare myself and my subject irrelevant by ignoring, and by failing to challenge, the students’ display of partisan certainty of being, one way or the other, on history’s right side, scarcely tolerating to be in one room with what was undeniably being construed as enemy forces, and vice versa? Was it not my duty, as a lecturer, to skip my prepared discussion of the subtleties of transcontinental anthropological fieldwork and its epistemological and moral dilemmas – suddenly rendered irrelevant and an act of navel-gazing self-indulgence. Should I not, instead, scrape together such perspectives on identity, globalisation, and reconciliation as I had already developed with a more specific focus on Africa, and on that basis try and improvise on how intercultural philosophy could begin to make sense of the devastating global moment we were all living through then, – bringing out how, perhaps, intercultural philosophy, of all subjects, could begin to illuminate the dilemmas of enmity, identity, ethics, justice, a shared world history and the apparent impossibility of reconciliation that were on the minds of all of us then? Anyway, the primary task forced upon me, that afternoon, was to try and apply whatever intercultural skills I could summon in such domains as emphathy, hermeneutics, chairmanship and discussion leadership, in order to make it possible that opinions and emotions from all the various relevant identitary positions present in the room, could be expressed, listened to, and discussed, in an orderly fashion, without any further violence, and as a basis for the semester of discussion and criticism that lay ahead of us. You may agree that, as a lecturer, I could not have hoped for a better kick-off to the next annual installment of my course on intercultural philosophy, than ‘9/11’, even though to say so would be most impious vis-a-vis the innumerable direct and indirect victims of 9/11, and, again, to say so  it would be most irresponsible in the face of the manipulation of public opinion by the media and governments, the rewriting of standards of accountability, of international law, of intergentile law, of human rights, of democracy, of the history of the crusades and of the jihads, during the nearly four years that have passed since ‘9/11’ –yet

                        The present argument originates in that afternoon of distress, heated debate and unexpected illumination (or apparent illumination) four years ago; meanwhile the initial improvisation has been somewhat enriched by subsequent reflection and scholarly debate.

                        As, probably, the most traumatic single event occurring in the North Atlantic region since the assassination of John Kennedy in 22 November 1963, or even since the Japanese attack on Pearl Harbour on 7 December 1941, ‘9/11’ is multi-faceted. Its overwhelming effects of mobilisation and counter-mobilisation lie largely outside the realm of discursive academic work anyway, and within the academic domain these effects touch on many disciplines apart from philosophy. The literature on the event is already too voluminous to review in our present scope. As a key event involving a significant, and politically dominant, part of the northern hemisphere, nothing short of a comprehensive analysis of our globalising world today would do justice to the event. Meanwhile, many essential details constituting the event itself have remained obscure and contradictory, and the subsequent intercontinental political and military developments suggest that this state of affairs cannot be expected to change in the immediate future.

                        It would be futile to hope that a philosophical discussion would throw unexpected light on an event that has rapidly become the most stereotyped and the most appropriated in contemporary history. Only at the cost of extreme academic facetiousness is it possible to indicate the event with another term than the pet designation it soon received in the USA media: ‘9-11’, linguistically an unmistakable Americanism no one is even aware of any more. Trivialisation, and the subtle conjuring open, with well-phrased academese apotropaeic formulae, of already wide open doors, are genuine dangers besetting the present argument. ‘9-11’ is a powerful common referent, an almost inescapable collective representation throughout the world today (although, inevitably, experienced and valued in radically different ways at the various opposing identitary and combative positions the event itself has first expressed, then engendered in its own turn). My principal aim is not to systematically deconstruct the notion of such an event as ‘9-11’ as the outcome – although that is clearly what it is – of complex and contradictory strategies of identitary mobilisation executed, not so much by national or religious collectivities, but by various intellectual, media, political and military elites situated at, or at least entertaining close virtual association with, various places on the globe today. To bring out the details of such manipulative strategies amounts to a project of empirical knowledge production, which with all its philosophical implications is hardly philosophical in the first place. I will leave such a task to competent others, and take ‘ 9-11’ rather for granted, even though this involves the risk of uncritically regurgitating manipulated collective representations, rather than (as is the philosopher’s task) exposing them. I take this risk, on the understanding that in order to make one or two specific points in a short paper, one must be prepared so skip over hundreds of more equally interesting or  more interesting points. There is however at least one respect in which I refuse to take over the common North Atlantic parlance in regard of ‘9-11’. Even though I condemn the related acts of violence of ‘ 9-11’ as much as the acts of violence that preceded or followed ‘9-11’, I will not employ the term ‘terrorism’ to describe ‘9/11’; for ‘terrorism’ smacks of an evaluative ethical position already taken, a verdict already pronounced, a partisan position that can only be one-sided, as an invitation to further violence.

                        What are the challenges that ‘9-11’ puts before intercultural philosophy? How does ‘9-11’ bring us to formulate an approach to intercultural philosophy that has is serious and relevant in the sense that it addresses, and seeks to philosophically articulate, some of the most urgent problems and predicaments of the world today?

2. Culture, identity, globalisation 

Intercultural philosophy is the branch of philosophy that was explicitly established, in the last few decades, in order to address philosophically the globalisation of difference.

                        I draw attention to the shift away from ‘culture’ as its initial central focus of research in intercultural philosophy, even though this was the eponymic element. We may define ‘culture’as  as ‘everything an person derives, through social as distinct from genetic transmission, from the society that person belongs to’ – Tylor)As I have argued at length elsewhere (van Binsbergen 1999a, 1999b, 2003), the social-scientific concept of culture  however illuminating and initially liberating in itself, has become too much appropriated by all varieties of actors in modern local, national and intercontinental political arenas (largely informed by the politics of recognition) than that it can still function adequately as a philosophical concept. Moreover, much of what actors claim, in such arenas today, to be their ‘culture’ to which they allegedly owe unmitigated allegiance and for which they demand the unmitigated respect of others, often turns out to consist  of selected, arbitrary, situational, performative and ephemeral, mere boundary markers of explicit difference, scarcely covering a much more undifferentiated cultural continuity in which such actors share which numerous others even though the latter would tend to claim different cultural identities for themselves. It is within this culturally unmarked continuous space, much more than in the particularist culturally marked and bounded space of distinct proclaimed identities, that people are capable to live a complete life, across the time-span from conception to grave and, on a daily basis, around the 24 hours of the clock – during which they continually move in and out of specific particularist spaces (family, workplace, sports club, peer group, place of worship, street, public transport, media, music, Internet, etc.), all the while pre-empting on the overarching existence of the continous common space, whose linguistic, social and technological premisses they have usually mastered to a considerable degree of effectiveness, and that usually without being greatly hindered by the specificity of the particularist spaces which they move in and out of several times a day. ‘Cultural’ claims thus have become short-hand for particularist identitary claims within an essentially pluralist and globalising socio-cultural space. And although the continuous globalising space is punctuated in terms of myriad identitary specificities, in other words consists of the articulation and negotiation of difference on a global scale, many of these identities are not strictly speaking cultural in the accepted sense.

                        What, then, is globalisation? If today we have the feeling that globalisation expresses a real and qualitative change that uniquely characterises our common condition, it is because state of the art  technology (typically in the trappings of capitalist commodification), which has brought about unprecedented levels of mastery of space and time. When messages travel at light speed across the globe using electronic media, when therefore physical displacement is hardly needed for effective communication yet such displacement can be effected within one or two days from anywhere on the globe to anywhere else, and when the technology of manufacturing and distribution has developed to such levels that the same material environment using the same objects can be created and fitted out anywhere on the globe at will — then we have reduced the fees that time and space impose on the social process, to virtually zero. Then we can speak of globalisation in the narrower  sense.

                        Globalisation is not about the absence or dissolution of boundaries, but about the dramatically reduced fee imposed by time and space, and thus the opening up of new spaces and new times within new boundaries that were hitherto inconceivable. Globalisation as a condition of the social world today revolves on the interplay between unbounded world–wide flow, and the selective framing of such flow within particularising  localising contexts of identity, of difference (cf. van Binsbergen 1997: 1f)

                        It is in the specific field of the globalisation of difference that the dramatic events summarised as ‘ 9-11’ represent the greatest challenges. My argument will review some of these challenges, and propose very tentative responses within the framework of my personal approach to intercultural philosophy:

3. ‘9-11’ approached from intercultural philosophy

a) Hermeneutics

Hermeneutics (i.e. the art of explaning human phenomena by vicariously articulating what they seem to mean for the actors who originally produced them) has been a standard intercultural approach; what is its potential, and what its limitations, if brought to berar upon the global contradictions under consideration here?

                        One recent example of a hermeneutical approach to ‘9-11’ is from Richard Kearney. Working at the forefront of hermeneutical philosophy, widely known, inter alia, as mediator in seminal round tables on the gift and on forgiveness around Derrida and Marion, and combining a professorial position in Ireland with one in Boston, U.S.A., Professor Kearney is particularly well situated to reflect on the way out from the aporia generated by 9/11’. With the article under discussion here (Kearney 2005), he does so in a recent article in the Journal of Interdisciplinary Crossroads, published in South Asia yet electronically circulating world-wide, which adds another element of potentially global relevance to his argument.

                        As a context for his hermeneutics of ‘ 9-11’, Kearney  takes for granted that ‘9/11’ is to have an effect on inter-religious dialogue.  He suggests that what he considers the perpetrators’ misappropriation of religion (of Islam, specifically) ought to be countered by a corresponding re-appropriation of non-violence among the other camp – loosely but significantly identified by him as ‘us’, ‘we’.  Unmistakably, Kearney’s ‘we’ means mainly ‘U.S.A. citizens and others identifying with them’, including himself. Admittedly he qualifies the ‘we’ perspective in several ways: it should not imply condoning the torture of Iraqi and Guantanamo Bay prisoners; it should not imply the mutual demonisation in which not only the perpetrators but also the U.S.A. leadership have publicly engaged; it should combine a Christian inspiration with a Buddhist, Hinduist, and Graeco-Roman classical one, and even have some room for Muslim mysticism; it should not be entrapped in a naïve ‘we’/’them’ dichotomy; it should not fall into the Huntington (1996) trap of conceptualising the conflict in terms of a clash of civilisations (but neither overstress pardon at the expense of justice, i.e. trial and punishment). Yet despite all these qualifications, the ‘we’ in Kearney’s argument remains a North Atlantic ‘we’ that is loyal to U.S.A. concerns. It does not shun from criticism of the U.S.A. leadership, it does acknowledge the existence (but scarcely the contents) of a highly critical assessment of the U.S.A. performance like Virilio’s (2002), yet carefully matches such criticism with ample attention for no-nonsense patriotic statements of such hawks as Dooley and Hitchens, who are cited in (apparent?) approval. Even for an Irish intellectual there are, apparently, limits to what one can write if one has a part-time professorship at Boston, which is from whose airport the ‘9/11’ airplanes took off on their way to destruction.

                        However, given his practical commitment to U.S.A. society Kearney probably needs to wrap up his unmistakable criticism in this way. He needs to create a context of mainstream credibility in which he can yet pose his question ‘How do we even begin to imagine pardoning Bin Laden?’ without immediately disqualifying this question as rhetorical, as implying ‘such pardon is impossible to imagine under whatever circumstances’.

                        It is Kearney’s hermeneutical position that is primarily responsible for his seeing ‘9/11’, legitimately, as a religious event: he is merely representing the protagonists’ own views of the matter. The demonising idioms, the emotional repertoire of images, employed by the leadership on both sides suggest that one is not dealing here with a secular conflict but with one saturated with religious overtones, on both sides. ‘Axis of Evil’ (in the idiom employed by the U.S.A. leadership) is not a secular but a religious term. Yet I suggest we must go beyond what Kearney advocates: we must not only apply our hermeneutics to the religious imagery here which we may at first have risked to ignore, – we must also take our distance from the actors’ religious imagery and see what implications it has for understanding, controlling, and resolving this intercontinental conflict that has already claimed many thousands of lives and that threatens to endanger world peace for decades to come. The gain of empathy and representation inherent in the hermeneutical position, may also be its loss: it allows us the identification and exegesis of the protagonists’ public pronouncements, but does not allow us to speak of their hidden or dissimilated agenda’s, let alone to analyse, distantly and objectifyingly, the political economy and other structural constraints to which the protagonists may be argued to be subjected even without them consciously, explicitly realising so – or without us having evidence that they do. In terms of an established usage in cultural anthropology (cf. Headland et al. 1990), hermeneutics allows us an emic analysis but not an etic one. The dilemma also reminds us of the classic Gadamer/Habermas debate of the 1960s-1970s – of which Ricoeur has been a major commentator.

                        If, complementary to a hermeneutical perspective, we would feel free to adopt a distancing analytical perspective, we would ask ourselves whether the ‘9/11’ confrontation between the (dominant elites of the) North Atlantic region and the world of militant Islam, in addition to the emic religious overtones, is not also a rational conflict over scarce resources in the political and economic domain (on the U.S.A. side: solidarity with Israel, a new phase of geopolitical expansion into the Middle East, and reliance – for industry and for highly-valued individual mobility – on cheap mineral oil; on the side of the militant Islamists: acknowledgment of historical wrongs done to Muslims in recent global history, and recognition of the validity of the view that Islam as a path through modernity and globalisation offers a valid alternative to dominant North Atlantic patterns). Such an analytical perspective would do something very important that is utterly beyond the hermeneutical approach: it would allow us to view ‘9/11’ in terms of global hegemony and counter-hegemony. In more practical terms, it would make it possible to contemplate the extent to which the U.S.A. leadership themselves may have been partly responsible for the escalation leading to ‘9/11’, so that the firm rhetorical distinction between perpetrators and victims begins to dissolve, and one obvious (if only partial) way out after ‘9/11’ would become discernable: trying to undo, on both sides, the conditions that led to such escalation.

                        For Kearney the fact that the ‘9/11’ conflict has profound religious aspects, means not that it is unsolvable (Huntington), but, quite to the contrary, enables Kearney to point at the potential of religion to cross or overcome boundaries and to move towards reconciliation. In that respect his approach is far more sympathetic than Huntington’s.  It is as if Kearney is saying:

‘you who are casting your post-’’9-11’’ enmity in a religious (Christian and Islamic)  idiom, and who are capitalising on the perennial association between religion and violence,[3] please realise that the same idiom contains such elements as would allow you to overcome your enmity – and, incidentally, the same elements also appear in other religions and worldviews, e.g. in those of South Asia’.

                        This is meaningful, even profound. Yt two crucial conditions continue to inform the situation and render Kearney’s recommendations rather ineffective:

1.      Kearney’s overall appeal to wisdom traditions’ hermeneutical tolerance fails to identify the specific social, political and communicative conditions under which the parties involved may reject, or may be prepared to adopt, the proposed shift from a conflictive and boundary-emphasising to a boundary-crossing and reconciliatory selection from among the repertoire of their respective religion, as exponents of the long history of wisdom traditions in the world. Kearney’s strategy in his argument – even though it is published in a South Asian venue – is to address those in the North Atlantic with Christian, Buddhist and Hinduist identifications or sympathies, and show them – with considerable erudition and eloquence – how here a road to hermeneutic tolerance may be found which would allow them (‘us’) to forgive the perpetrators (but see above) of ‘9/11’. It is somewhat unfortunate that Kearney’s hermeneutical perspective does not extend beyond the dominant groups in the North Atlantic region, especially not to Muslims in general (including those many millions of Muslims currently residing in the North Atlantic region), let alone the militant Islamists who most probably were behind the ‘9/11’ attacks. Only towards the end of his argument there is a passing admittance that also Islamic spirituality provides examples of the same hermeneutic tolerance that Kearney advocates as the way out. His argument would have been much more impressive if he would have explicitly addressed the crucial question as to what kind of perspective (religious, political, economic) one would have to offer to Muslims, and to militant Islamists particularly, in order to bring them to the point where reconciliation becomes possible and past deeds may be brought to redressive and reintegrative, properly judicial  trial in mutual recognition of their unacceptability. Moreover, it would have been an impressive display of intercultural sensitivity if Kearney had acknowledged traditions of reconciliation world-wide, including those outside the established literate world religions, e.g. in the African and Native American context.[4] Kearney’s plea to let the world’s wisdom traditions do the work of reconciliation would have been more effective if this plea had not stressed the North Atlantic region, philosophical and Christian/ theological tradition so ethnocentrically – which is where his short excursion into South Asian wisdom traditions soon takes Kearney. If he mentions mysticism, why miss the golden opportunity of exploring Islamic mysticism (al-DJili, ibn al-‘Arabi, al-Hallaj, al-GHazzali, etc.) as a possible source of a wisdom that could well be persuasive to militant Islamists. If he mentions Aristotle, why not exploit the fact that Aristotle was transmitted to the North Atlantic through Islamic thinkers and left traces in Islamic thought even after al-Ghazzali had concluded the victory of theology over philosophy, in the world of Islam? The existence of an extensive and enduring Islamic wisdom tradition (Sufism, associated with its exponents’ woollen – Arab. suf – garments according to some popular etymology, but in fact the pursuit of (Greek) sophia, ‘wisdom’) is largely ignored by Kearney. This is all the more regrettable, because Sufism, much more than the formal conceptual and confrontational thought of militant Islamism, has been the popular Islam of the Middle Eastern and North African masses for almost a millennium now.[5]

2.      The public underpinning of either side’s post-’9/11’ position by reference to a religious idiom may be only a minority option. Kearney seems to preach for his own parish, which not only is limited to dominant groups in the North Atlantic region, but among the latter, to those with a Christian or South Asian religious identity or at least sympathy. Given high levels of secularisation, the set thus defined only comprises a minority of the current population of the North Atlantic region. How are the secularised others to be involved,[6] including those who prefer to see the Christian idiom employed by the U.S.A. leadership as mere rhetoric? How are Muslims to be involved, without first being blackmailed into having to publicly denounce the militant Islamists and the, admittedly totally unacceptable, extremes to which the latter went in the context of ‘9/11’? Surely it would be an interreligious naivety, not to say insult, to expect Muslims to let other religious orientations than Islam inspire them towards an attitude of reconciliation that is, in the most literal sense, at the very heart of Islam. Are we seriously to consider the polysemy of the Judaeo-Christian Bible’s Song of Songs, to which Kearney refers, as an argument that is going to win Muslims over towards reconciliation? Moreover (contrary to some of the examples Kearney gives: Griffith, Makransky, Tolstoy), the sensitivity politics of interreligious and intercultural hermeneutics would certainly abhor a situation where outsiders, strangers to one’s own religious tradition are claimed to occupy a privileged vantage point from where to interpret one’s own religious tradition; such a claim smacks of condescension and hegemony – it does not do to tell others what their identity is (cf. van Binsbergen 2003b). How are Muslims to be involved in the post-’9/11’ reconciliation process, on the basis of their own spiritual traditions? This is for Muslims to say; and all non-Muslims need to do is to reserve seats for Muslims around the table, far more explicitly and generously than Kearney has managed to do in his argument, even though his argument was clearly written in the same spirit as my recommendation on this point.

                        Kearney’s plea for hermeneutical tolerance is sympathetic, timely and well-taken, but we need to be far more specific if we want it to work. The hermeneutical recognition of polysemy alone is not the answer to ‘9-11’. The point is not that words can be interpreted in so many ways at the same time. The point is, for instance, that, in the modern world, hardened positions of exclusion and enmity represent a violence of words simultaneous with – often even preceding – the physical violence of deeds, while state-of-the-art technologies lend to these violent words an unprecedented new power by diffusing them all over the globe, at the same time lending the technological means to bring them into violent practice. And the point is to recognise militant Islamism, not as an inevitable and perennial core of Islam, but as a recent and relatively deviant ideological product of the very same globalisation of our times[7] as has lend, to militant Islamism, its singularly widespread appeal (through globalised media) and (in the sense of von Trotha’s 2003 argument) its singularly material destructiveness. Militant Islamism, as a performative and thus deliberately atavistic revival of jihadist tendencies of the times of the Prophet Muh?ammad, is not the intrinsic nor the inevitable format of contemporary Islam, but a mutative re-invention, the result of the marriage between Islam and recent globalisation.

                        Anyway, given the links between words and violence, one place where reconciliation may be found is in the interstices between words and between messages, in silence.

                        But that is not the only place.

                        As Kearney suggests, a legal framework ensuring fair trial may also be a way to bring about ultimate reconciliation, and would certainly not stand in the latter’s way. I do agree on this point, and I am reminded of a case where the emphatic insistence on non-violent patterns of confession, forgiving and reconciliation, rather than on lawful punishment, may have prevented the catharsis that is needed for a true overcoming of the violence of the past: the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission.[8] But, much like I myself in the latter work cited, Kearney does not give the reasons why pardon should be complemented by justice – he simply tells us that this is what Ricoeur posits.[9]

                        Undeniably, by North Atlantic national versions of public law, and by the human rights code adopted by the great majority of states in the hope of thus rendering it universal, the perpetrators of ‘9/11’ acted criminally; yet in their own eyes they must have considered themselves legitimated by reference to some higher law, and in the process they were prepared to sacrifice not only other peoples’ lives but also their own. Reconciliation is only possible if we do not deny this conflict of perceptions of legality, but if, instead, we actively invent a discourse (cf. van Binsbergen 2003b, especially the introduction) in which, through creative symbolic sleight-of-hand, both perspectives may be recognised, accommodated and overcome. This is a way in which hermeneutics can still be of considerable value in the present contexts, and this I will explore towards the end of my argument, when coming back to reconciliation.

                        Meanwhile, as the next step in my argument, let me explore the extent to which globalisation as a  frame of reference is illuminating for ‘9-11’.

b) The puzzle of holist particularism in globalisation

Although to the outside observer (particularly if informed by the philosophy of difference) the definition of an identitary position in the context of globalisation may be accidental, this is not necessarily – not even typically – how such a position appears, subjectively, to those who hold it. Meaning (and indeed, philosophy) is constructed within a local space that is considered ‘home’, and within which the degree of meaningfulness is directly related to

  1. the extent to which that meaning is shared by others, and
  2. the extent to which that meaning encompasses as many aspects of the local experience as possible.

Boundaries are created in order to protect local meaning, and physical practices (rituals) are engaged in to inscribe these meanings so effectively into corporal and collective experiences so as to render them subjectively inescapable – in other words, real.   

Many an identitary position, and (because of the ritual effectiveness of their collective en-corporation practices) especially many a religious identity in the modern world hinges on the following dilemma: it is world-creating, cosmogonic, in the sense that it offers the concepts, the collective representations, to articulate a world, and to make that world alive and real to those who carry that culture or adhere to that religion. One cannot create a part world, any more than one can claim oneself to be a part person. World creation implies the pretense of universality. But these claims of universality, of a totalising world picture, are fostered – and there is the paradox – not by the whole of humanity, but typically only by a small subset of humanity. The world creation of the one obliterates, implies the absolute denia  of, the world creation of the other. It lays claims to absolute and total truth (the truth of Islam, the absolute respect due to such as representative democracy, human rights, the Prophet Muhammad, or the Qur’an), and that is when opposite positions of absolute, irresolvable difference are being created. 

                        It is here that modern globalisation invites a radical mutation of the experience. As a long as various identitary world-creating constructs could live at a considerable distance from each other  without being effectively thrown together as part of the same continuous globalising space, there was not much of a problem – the other remained sufficiently distant so as not to threaten (as an intolerable alternative, and as a refutation of the home logic underpinning the entire home world), one’s own local holist particularism, one’s own world creation. Globalisation however brings out, and drives home, the incompatibilities of various holist particularisms, reinforces the tendencies for each to entrench into itself with increasing hostility towards the outside, and to oppose and confront the other with which it has now been brought to direct confrontation for the first time. The hardening of identitary conflict today has little to do with any inherent tolerance in North Atlantic democratic / neo-liberal ideology, or with any inherent tolerance in Islam. That hardening is rather a product of a modern condition of our present, early phase of total globalisation, and it may be intensified to such a degree as to result, as a mutation, in the absolute mutual intolerance known from recent years. Now one is competing for the same global space, and for unique all-encompassing truth, for a coherent an credible world, within that same space – so now that conflict becomes a matter of life and death, in a zero-sum game, where – in the subjective awareness of the actors involved – the existence of the one precludes the existence of the other, and calls for the latter’s annihilation. Moreover, effective annihilation has now come within reach, on both sides, with the omnipresence realised by modern electronic and digital media, and with the unprecedented killing capacity of modern weaponry.   

                        But if the underlying conflict is really structurally caused, in a very formal way, by the fact that the present state of globalisation can no longer accommodate the habitual forms of world creation through holist particularism, then we have reached the limit to the relevance of  hermeneutics in this connection: if the primary cause of the conflict is formal and structural, then the actual specific contents of world making, and the modalities of their incompatibility, hardly matter – it is not what world is being constructed, but that that world construction is local and universalising/totalising at the same time, but now in a globalised situation where the illusion of the local is even less tenable than ever before.   

                        And if the conflict is really an effect of the ills of globalisation in this way, then an obvious way out suggests itself:   

 

In this respect ‘9-11’, however tragic in its intransigent juxtaposition of enemy positions, and however intolerable as massive mortal violence, also comes as a timely and serious reminder that any attempt to push the success of the North Atlantic hegemonic project any further is utterly pointless and will merely lead to the destruction of the global texture – just as one cannot have a texture that is all warp and no woof.  The identitary position of militant Islam is not a rejection of modern rationality, and least of all of the science and technology which that rational has created, but of geopolitical submission to the North Atlantic region.  It is a refusal to accept the end of history.

                        Meanwshile two factors make it immensely difficult to create (or rather, since it has already been created ever since the League of Nations in the 1920s, to sustain) the overarching, global frameworkl to accommodate the positions of identitary difference around ‘9/11’:

  1. The conscious identitary element masks a political economyu which needs to be admitted, in its overriding primarcy, in the first place;
  2. Illuminating as the insight in identity’s strategic performativity may be, it has, on both sides, a firm limitation in the historicity of identity formation through violence; this, in its turn, may also suggest a way out, but along rather different lines.

This means that, although we cannot legitimately invoke an enduring, cultural, normative basis for the hardening of positions of difference on either side, and although we can relegat the conflict to the formal deficienceis of holistic particularism in this present phase of globalisation, still such entrenchment cannot be treated lightly as if it were ‘ merely performative’. As a downright mutation, among small but powerful elites, of pre-existing, enduring normative systems of collectivities, the idiosyncratic thought procedures that, for the violent and intransigeant actors themselves, create new justifications of violence are to be appreciated as products of globalisation, cast in a format that is new and global, rather than local and atavistic.  But subsequently they are rendered real, and sacred, because of the pain inflicted and the blood shed in the process of contestation itself.  

c) Towards reconciliation

When – as in the case of ‘ 9/11’ – a small set of humans are brought to violate widespread and fundamental codes such as the respect for human lives, for civilians, for the latter’s beloved ones, for other people’s property and the fruits of human labour (in the form of buildings and airplanes), for the orderly conduct of armed conflict, and even turn out to be prepared to sacrifice their own lives in the process, then, in principle, the whole of humanity qualifies as victims – materially, by association, vicariously, and by implication; and this even includes the perpetrators themselves, whose sense of historical injury and dehumanising hatred we, the other humans, can only begin to fathom inside ourselves. This implies the possibility of a ‘we’ that encompasses the whole of mankind, and that contains in itself the conditions for all suffering and for all reconciliation. It is here that we may yet press hermeneutics into service.

                        Thus in principle Kearney is right in his claim that hermeneutic tolerance may be the way out of protracted violent conflicts such as in Palestine/ Israel, Northern Ireland, Bosnia, and by implication, ‘9/11. In this connection Kearney cites, as an instance of hermeneutic tolerance, the founding of Christianity in the formal, collective acceptance, by Jesus’ earliest followers, of Paul’s universalism’. Yet this example has only limited applicability to such modern situations, pace Kearney. For although that foundational situation may have considerable appeal to Christians as a model for emulation, it was very small-scale, and it particularly lacked the history of accumulated collective violent trauma in a conscious, identity-constructing historic process, which characterises all such protracted modern conflicts including that leading on to, and following, ‘9/11’. It is the historicity of identity formation through violence, which we have to deal with in the context of ‘9/11’, on both sides; and that has no parallels in the New Testament except perhaps (obliquely and in largely unarticulated form) in the confrontation between Jews and Romans (which, more than Paul’s universalism, may well have been the prime factor in the emergence of Christianity). Moreover, the subsequent two millennia of Christian-Jewish relations (which, without much exaggeration, may be summarised as a long chain of intolerance, exclusion and violence inflicted upon Jews by Christians) has shown that Paul’s universalism has seldom allowed his spiritual heirs, the Christians, to effectively mobilise a similar hermeneutic tolerance towards the co-religionists of the founder of Christianity, the Jew Yoshua bar Miriam. Nor has the appeal to such hermeneutic tolerance, however admittedly foundational to Christianity (Badiou’s idea (2003) as cited by Kearney is correct but far from new), inspired the proclaimedly Christian U.S.A. leadership to employ that attitude in its stance vis-à-vis the perpetrators of ‘9-11’.

                        Therefore, after identifying this kind of hermeneutical tolerance as one of the ways out, Kearney would have been expected to spell out how it can be practically deployed in the present situation, by Christians not automatically practicing it, and by Muslims not likely to be impressed by it as long as it is presented in specifically Christian trappings. Of course Kearney far from suggests that such hermeneutical tolerance is specifically Christian: indeed, as I have myself argued elsewhere (van Binsbergen 2003a), any conflict resolution involving reconciliation depends on it, and it is particularly small-scale African societies that can be shown to have developed this socio-communicative technology to high levels of perfection. In my argument cited, I also explore the inner mechanisms of such reconciliation. These turn out to involve, inter alia:

1.      the recognition that both sides in the conflict are, by their own standards and perceptions, right, and act in rational integrity;

2.      secondly, the only way to reconcile two such positions is by a hermeneutics that is not only tolerant, but that is to be emphatically inventive and innovative: a new overarching discourse needs to be invented that, in the eyes of both parties, dissolves their irreconcilable positions of incompatible rightness into compromise – which requires a skilful and inspired, charismatic act of social communicative sleight-of-hand;

3.      as already indicated above, this can only be done by virtue of both parties recognising and affirming each other’s common humanity which they share – putting an end to all earlier rhetoric of mutual demonisation.

We note that in this conception of reconciliation, hermeneutics is employed,

1)      not so much for explaining, in retrospect, what the protagonists in the conflict do think, and what their hidden motives are, but 

2)      for inventing, i.e. by creatively and deliberately thinking beyond their present position, what they should think in order to make the conflict resolvable.  

In fact, what may be proposed as the way out of ‘9/11’, amounts to a move, away from the immature globalisation of holistic, universalising particularism and its delusions of a zero-sum game of extermination of the other, and towards the creation of a new and effective (finally worldwide) framework in which (much like ethnicity in any national or regional context) one accepts one’s own proclaimed identity to exist, pluralistically, alongside several or many others – and where one can truly accept such a state of affairs with peace of mind, in the certitude that one’s identity is safeguarded by the overall framework. Here an analogy with regional and national ethnicity in the African context may be illuminating. One of the important lessons to be learned from post-colonial politics in Africa – rife with ethnic conflict as the national framework of difference, often to the point of secession, sometimes genocide – is that ethnicity can usually be contained, may even constitute an integrative and productive force in nation states, as long as the overall structural framework survives of which the constituent ethnic groups form part and within which they oppose each other without destroying each other. The explosive, fatal situations arise only when one of the constituent ethnic groups gains absolute control of the overall framework, and appropriates it, but appropriating the state and its instruments of violence, sanction and legitimation. By analogy, globalisation (as the emerging overall framework of difference at a world scale) risks to become destructive as soon as one of the constituent units within the global structure can totally control the rest: as soon as, specifically, the global hegemonic project of the North Atlantic region comes close to success. Then we would have truly the end of history, but in a sense that warps Fukuyama’s Hegelian understanding in a distorting mirror.   

                        If (in the field of technology, child care, medicine, the environment, the exchange of musical, dancing and pictorial art forms, the debate on global justice, on collective guilt and reconciliation, the shared historical spiritual roots of Islam, Judaism and Christianity, the shared linguistic background of Christianity’s Indo-European and Islam’s Afro-Asiatic as, presumably, branches of the linguistic macrofamily of Nostratic, or whatever other argument) a framework could be forged in which North Atlantic secular, nominally democratic neo-liberalism, and militant Islam, could exist and function side by side, ‘9-11’ could be written away in history as a tragic reminder of an earlier, immature phase of globalisation finally left behind us.

                        Following Ricoeur, and in a way remarkably similar to mine yet somewhat less concrete and practical, Kearney sees four benefits to come from an hermeneutics of tolerance:

1.      an ethic of narrative hospitality (cf. my ‘recognition of a shared humanity’);

2.      an ethic of narrative flexibility (cf. my ‘sleight-of-hand’);

3.      narrative plurality (cf. my recognition that both parties are right and endowed with rational integrity);

4.      the transfiguring of the past (cf. my ‘creative and innovative’); and is to ultimately lead on to

5.      ‘exceptional moments (...) where an ethics of justice is touched by a poetics of pardon’.

                        I could not agree more. What is involved is really an exercise in rhetoric in the original Aristotelian sense (cf. van Binsbergen 2004): presenting a rational political argument in such a skilful way – seeking to effectively convince them, but not necessarily by hollow or false arguments – that it may persuade fellow actors in the political arena.

                        Yet again we hit on the ominous ‘we’: for ‘us’, it is difficult to forgive the perpetrators of ‘9/11’ – but where is the empathic argument that makes their position at least understandable, and would allow ‘them’ to forgive ‘us’, or would allow humanity (‘history’) to forgive both ‘them’ and ‘us’?

References

Badiou, Alain, 2003. St Paul:The Foundations of Universalism, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press..

Bewaji, J.A.I., & Ramose, M.B., 2003, ‘The Bewaji, Van Binsbergen and Ramose debate on ubuntu’, South African Journal of Philosophy, 22, 4: 378-415.

Headland, T.N., Pike, K.L., & Harris, M., 1990, eds., Emics and etics: The insider/outsider debate, Frontiers of Anthropology no. 7, Newbury Park/ London/ New Delhi: Sage.

Huntington, Samuel, 1996, The clash of civilizations and the remaking of the world order, New York: Simon & Schuster.

Kearney, Richard, 2001. The God Who May Be: A Hermeneutics of Religion. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

Kearney, Richard, 2005, ‘Thinking After Terror: An Interreligious Challenge’, Journal of the Interdisciplinary Crossroads, 2, 1 (April, 2005): 1-24.

Massignon, L., 1922, La Passion d’Al-Hallaj, ii vols., Paris; English version: The Passion of al-Hallaj, 4 vols., Bollingen Series, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983

Ngwane, George, 1996, Settling disputes in Africa: Traditional bases for conflict resolution, Yaounde: Buma Kor.

Salazar, Philippe-Joseph, Sanya Osha, Wim van Binsbergen, 2004, eds., Truth in Politics, Rhetorical Approaches to Democratic Deliberation in Africa and beyond, special issue: Quest: An African Journal of Philosophy, XVI, pp. 238-272; also at: http://www.quest-journal.net/2002.htm

van Binsbergen, Wim M.J., 1981, Religious Change in Zambia: Exploratory studies, London/Boston: Kegan Paul International.

van Binsbergen, Wim M.J., 2001a, ‘Witchcraft in modern Africa as virtualised boundary conditions of the kinship order’, in: Bond, G.C., & Ciekawy, D.M., eds., Witchcraft dialogues: Anthropological and philosophical exchanges, Athens (Ohio): Ohio University Press, pp. 212-263; also at: http://www.shikanda.net/african_religion/witch.htm

van Binsbergen, Wim M.J., 2001b, ‘Ubuntu and the globalisation of Southern African thought and society’, in: Boele van Hensbroek, P., ed., African Renaissance and Ubuntu Philosophy, special issue of: Quest: An African Journal of Philosophy, 15, 1-2, 2001: 53-89; also at: http://www.quest-journal.net/Quest_2001_PDF/binsbergen.pdf  

van Binsbergen, Wim M.J., 2003a, ‘Reconciliation: Ideas and procedures constituting the African social technology of shared and recognised humanity’, in: van Binsbergen 2003b: 349-374; earlier version available at: http://www.shikanda.net/african_religion/reconcil.htm  

van Binsbergen, Wim M.J., 2003b, Intercultural encounters: African and anthropological lessons towards a philosophy of interculturality, Berlin/Müenster, LIT; in part available at: http://www.shikanda.net/intercultural_encounters/index.htm   

van Binsbergen, Wim M.J., 2004, ‘Postscript: Aristotle in Africa – Towards a Comparative Africanist reading of the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission’, in: Salazar et al. 2004: 238-272; also at: http://www.quest-journal.net/2002.htm

van Binsbergen, Wim M.J., & Schoffeleers, J.M., 1985, eds., Theoretical explorations in African religion, London/ Boston: Kegan Paul International.

Virilio, Paul, 2002, Ground Zero, London & New York: Verso.

von Trotha, Trutz, 2003, ‘ Wars of defeat from Hiroshima to 9/11’, in: van Binsbergen, W.M.J., ed., The dynamics of power and the rule of law: Essays on Africa and beyond, Berlin/Münster/London: LIT, pp. 263-284; cf. http://www.shikanda.net/ethnicity/just.htm 

 



[1] This is a slightly revised, but (due to pressure of time) still very rough version of my GIPh Lecture as presented.

Most of the very stimulating discussion at Groningen still needs to be implemented, but already I wish to thank the Faculty of Philosophy, Groningen University,

for a highly stimulating intellectual event, and a most cordial reception.

[2] Due to the restructuring of the philosophy curriculum at the Erasmus University Rotterdam, as from the academic year 2004-2005

my course has become a bachelor’s III course, and is now taught in Dutch; hence the otherwise surprising use of past tense.

[3] Kearney acknowledges the intellectual movement (Freud, Girard etc.) that sees religion as essentially a product of violence.

I have no quarrel with Kearney’s rendering of that movement, however succinct, but I think the idea behind the movement is utterly one-sided. Both Kearney (2001) and I

(van Binsbergen 1981, van Binsbergen & Schoffeleers 1985, and many later publications, largely available at http://www.shikanda.net) have written extensive theoretical

arguments on religion, and this is not the place for a debate on this point. Let me merely say this. In my opinion religion is not just about the transmutation or sublimation

of violence. It is an (apparently almost inevitable) by-product of human thought organised into patterned action and relatively stable metaphors. It is risky to make

presuppositions about an undocumented distant past (the Middle Palaeolithic) when we have evidence of interhuman violence but not of articulate speech. Yet under

contemporary, literate conditions it is safe to say that violence may be as much a product of discursive thought (inter alia, religious thought), as that discursive

thought (inter alia, religious thought) is a product of violence.

[4] On Africa, cf. Ngwane 1996; van Binsbergen 2003a.

[5] This is not an idle claim, but one based on my years of historical and ethnographical research on North African popular Islam, around

1970 – basis for a two-volume scholarly study now being finalised for publication.

[6] Failure to appreciate how the vast majority of the North Atlantic population is no longer actively committed to Christianity

or Judaism also affects other parts of Kearney’s argument. Thus he claims that the tolerance between adversaries is to be increased by the realisation that they both belong to

the Abrahamic tradition (but so do the opponents in the Northern Ireland conflict, and in most conflicts that have waged in Europe in the course of the last thousand years,

including Christians’ treatment of Jews throughout that period), and also (Ricoeur) by reading each others’ sacred scripture. Again, the latter recommendation is correct in

principle, but how is it going to have a genuine impact on the North Atlantic region today, and on North Atlantic / Muslim relations, if due to secularisation only a minority

of North Atlantic inhabitants identify as active adherents of the Christian and Jewish faith any more, while Islam is establishing itself, in the same region, rapidly and self-confidently?

Christianity may be the rhetorical and performative idiom of the U.S.A. leadership, but it is no longer the worldview of all U.S.A. citizens, let alone of all citizens of the rest

of the North Atlantic region.

[7] In other words, I propose to analyse today’s contemporary militant Islamism from the same perspective as that which I applied

elsewhere to Southern African ubuntu philosophy and to the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission; cf. van Binsbergen 2001b, 2004. My approach has

however generated considerable controversy, cf. Bewaji & Ramose 2003. 

[8] 1994-1998; cf. Salazar et al. 2004 with references to the extensive literature; van Binsbergen 2004.

[9]The obvious reason, not likely to be found with Ricoeur, is that the opponents on both sides bring to the conflict and its subsequent

reconciliation general notions of justice, punishment and retaliation which may be creatively addressed and negotiated in the course of reconciliation (especially by a skilful

outsider), but hardly so creatively as to totally eclipse or obliterate these notions; therefore, any reconciliation that does not take such particularistic notions of justice into

account, risks to remain on performative, unable to prevent that the conflict simmers on underneath as a form of resentment still demanding satisfaction.

[10] The plausibility of my analysis here is borne out by the fact that on both sides, the opponents in the ‘9-11’ conflict have dissimilated,

denied, and sought to escape from whatever overarching, global framework already exists. On the side of militant Islamism this is clear in the complete violation of intergentile

law and conventions of warfare, through the absence of a declaration of war, the absence of any post-war message annouoncing the perpetrators’ identity and their motives,

and the targetting of civilians. On the side of the USA (and subsequently, in what was typically an unsystematic, ad-hoc alliance, the UK) there has been the denial of the

binding nature of the global, treaty-supported institution of the United Nations Organisation, the launching of large-scale military attacks on two nations that, as nations,

had nothing demonstrably to do with the ‘9-11’ (Afghanistan and Iraq), and in the process ignoring vehement and massive international protests, while not even the

trouble was taken to invest the paper-thin pretexts as to the presence if mass destruction weapons with enough credibility to at least respect these democratic leadership’s

accountability to their own electorate. On both sides, the paramount message has been: there is no overarching framework of authority or legitimacy to which we are answerable,

it is just us against the enemy in mortal combat.

 

 

homepage

page last modified: 03-06-05 22:25:06 Bravenet.com